The significance of biology for the question concerning human nature
I – Introduction: ἄνθρωπον
ζητῶ
Since
Aristotle, humans are considered part of the natural world, φύσει ὄντα.[1]
As the question concerning human essence
as human nature became more and more
a question about human naturalness (in opposition to nurture, Spirit,
technology etc.), and, at the same time, our understanding of the natural world
became prerogative of “natural sciences”, philosophers have looked at biology
in their search for the human, and what makes them uniquely themselves.[2]
Since the philosophical question
about human nature claims to search for an all-inclusive universal answer, it
has looked at humans from the perspective of their natural kind, their species:
what’s the essence of Homo sapiens?
The problem is thus interpreted as that of biological
essentialism: because we assume that the essence of humans pertains to the
biological, we ask ourselves if our
species manifests anything like a biological essence (universal specific
properties etc.). In particular, we will look both at the classical view of
essences as constitutive intrinsic properties, and at the more recent attempt
at conciliating essentialism with the historical and dynamic character of
evolutionary species concepts. Given their failure, we will search for a
possible answer in the notion of innate nature.
The
grounding question we ask is: what kind of answer does biological science give
to the philosophical question about human nature? The discussion will be
divided in three parts:
-
a review of classical essentialism, with a
focus on the notions of universality
and normality and a detour through
Aristotle;
-
a review of the new essentialism and its
shortcomings;
-
a review of the notion of innateness.
II – Traditional essentialism
The
traditional western interpretation of the human as animal rationale puts humans among other living species (as animal), distinguished by them by virtue
of their differentia specifica (rationalitas), or their specific
essence. This way of looking at human nature is grounded in the traditional
link between essence and species. In particular, living species
have been the paradigmatic example of something with an essence, from Aristotle
to modern proponents of essentialism such as Putnam and Kripke.[3]
There is a good reason for this: not only does the living world seem (at first
glance) to be carved into natural joints, but, most importantly, living beings
provide a great example of substantiality. An essence explains why, no matter
how much it changes, a butterfly never loses its self-identity: it never stops
being a butterfly, it never loses its essence (until it dies).
At
the same time, however, the advent and expansion of the historical perspective
of Darwinian evolutionary biology seems to have marked once and for all the end
of species essentialism. Species originate, divide, merge, change, vary, die,
so they cannot have eternal and universal essences; their boundaries can be
blurred in many ways, both diachronically and synchronically, so they cannot
have a clear-cut differentia specifica.
Now,
essentialism is hard to die. An essence provides a link between the individual
living being and its species – the individuals we study shape our idea of a
species (its common characters and variations, its history), which then informs
our subsequent study of other individuals (it provides a ground for induction).
In other words, it plays both a semantic role
(“Homo sapiens” refers to a universal
property of the species, that is, a property supposed to belong to all the
members of the species – the same way “water” refers to H2O) and a causal/explanatory role (what it refers
to is what makes Homo sapiens the way
they are).[4]
Essences (or essential properties) can be intrinsic
(as per Aristotelian tradition) or relational
(as the “new essentialists” propose). Such ambitious role of essences begs the
question: does biology really inform us about properties that determine both
the species and the individual beings belonging to it at the same time?
In
1986, David Hull proposed an important critique of intrinsic essentialism in
biology in his paper On human nature.
In particular, he focused on the philosophers’ traditional criteria for a
proper human essence: universality and normativity. The philosopher complains:
“There must be characteristics which all
and only people exhibit, or at least potentially
exhibit, or which all normal people
exhibit – at least potentially”[5].
According
to Hull, essentialists assume that “some connection exists between universality
and innateness”[6],
perhaps because essence precedes any variation by definition, and what is not
innate is the result of developmental changes and varying external influences
(non intrinsic traits). Allegedly universal traits such as language are thus
assumed to be species-specific and therefore grounded in the human genome. Even
ignoring the fallacy of deducting specificity from innateness, it is possible
to see how the reference to the genotype-phenotype map does not grant us any
access to universals. Both phenotypes and genotypes are in fact neither
universal nor specific. First, a human might be incapable of language because
of lack of the necessary genetic underpinning (phenotypic and/or genetic
non-universality). Secondly, even if we tried to reintegrate this human through
an appeal to potentiality (“if they had a different genetic make-up…”),
according to Hull we could, by the same principle, integrate any other species.[7]
Thirdly, the view of human traits as inherently unique or “human” is dubious:
The traits (and genes) which characterize
all species save our own vary statistically. For some reason those characters
which make us what we truly are happen to be universally distributed among all
members of our species (at least potentially among normal human beings) and
absent in all other species. I find this coincidence highly suspicious.[8]
Phenotypic
and genotypic properties, from the biologist’s point of view, are in a
continuum across species: “Zebras and horses look very much alike, but
genetically they’re quite different. Human beings and chimpanzees look quite
different, but genetically we are almost identical”[9].
Similar phenotypes can have very different genetic underpinnings, as in the
case of analogous traits originated from convergent evolution; while similar
genetic make-up can be expressed with great variations, as in the case of
homologous traits. Hull’s perspective, in a word, seems to flatten out the
relationship of similarity and dissimilarity between species. For example,
assuming that we might recognise the same phenotype in organisms of
different species, such phenotype would not be intrinsically “zebra” or “horse”. A horse is not a horse because it is made of “horse traits”.
Therefore, the presence of one “horse” trait in a zebra does not make the
latter more “horse”. Most importantly though, Hull’s view presents a flatter
relationship even between individuals of the same species: as it is not the
lack of language in a chimpanzee that makes it less human, the lack of language
in a human does not make it less human than the rest of their fellow
conspecifics – exactly because the
appeal to potentiality is not an appeal to some sort of unexpressed human
essence.
Still,
the ways a human and a chimpanzee lack language still appear to be different -
the former seems “supposed” to have it, the latter does not. After all,
biologists can be surprised to find that a bee cannot develop its wings, but do
not usually wonder why a blue whale is wingless. As we have seen, Hull attributes
to the essentialist discourse an understanding of lack as potentiality (e.g. “Organisms that lack a particular trait
possess it potentially...”[10]). A
brief discussion of Aristotle’s concept of στέρησις can help us illuminate how
much the boundaries of classical essentialism can stretch - and why it really
fails. In Metaphysics V, Aristotle
presents the following examples:
We speak of "privation
(στέρησις)": (a) In one sense, if a thing does not possess an attribute
which is a natural possession, even
if the thing itself would not naturally possess it; e.g., we say that a
vegetable is "deprived" of eyes. (b) If a thing does not possess an
attribute which it or its genus would naturally possess. E.g., a blind man is
not "deprived" of sight in the same sense that a mole is; the latter
is "deprived" in virtue of its genus, but the former in virtue of
himself.[11]
First
of all, some traits are natural possessions (τι τῶν πεφυκότων), they are
possessed πε-φυκότως, and similarly they are lacked. Here we still cannot
interpret the natural possession or lack of traits as being in virtue of a
living’s nature (form, essence, be it general or specific): this sense of
privation only focuses on the trait, so to say, taken abstractly. A natural
possession is an “attribute”, a trait that, formally speaking, can be
had by an organism, e.g., eyes, an exoskeleton, a nesting behaviour, photosynthesis.
As we ask ourselves only whether the trait itself
is instantiated or not, we ignore the essence of the organism supposed to lack
it. According to this concept, a mole and a plant are equally eyeless, but not
insofar as they are moles or plants, but only because they are eyeless. This
first meaning of στέρησις signals the absence of a trait, which is
equally possible as its presence (again, we ignore the fact that an eyeless
plant, as a plant, can only be eyeless), and thus its formal possibility.
According
to its second meaning, στέρησις, on the contrary, is seen from the perspective
of the essence of the lacking organism. For Aristotle, an individual kiwi would
be flightless κατὰ τὸ γένος, according to its species[12], but
not flightless in itself. On the other hand, an individual human is blind καθ᾽αὑτό,
in virtue of themselves.[13]
How are we to understand this difference? In both cases the essence of the
organism is not indifferent. It is the essence of the kiwi that determines that
the kiwi is not lacking flight because of itself (for example, because of its
contingent development, because of illness or violence[14]),
but because it belongs to a taxon of flightless birds. Similarly, it is the
essence of a human that determines that their blindness, or lack of sight, is,
so to say, something missing, not determined by the human species, but
caused by the human themselves. Both the flightless kiwi and the blind human
are lacking a trait for what they concretely are, but in different senses: the
kiwi is flightless because it is a kiwi; on the contrary, as humans do
have sight, a human is blind because they are able to miss it. According to
this sense of στέρησις, the way a human can have the trait they lack is
different from the way a trait can be present or absent. Because of their
essence, a human has the concrete possibility of having a trait,
and therefore, of missing it.
In an
essentialist context, a flightless kiwi is a normal kiwi, but perhaps an
atypical bird. Is a blind human normal? To the extent that sight is not a
specifically human character, that is, it is not assumed to be the
species-defining differentia specifica, its lack is not said to deprive
a human of what makes them so – a lack like blindness is taken as
uncontroversial.
However,
if something like language is specific and essential to humans, blindness and
lack of language might be two different kinds of privation. According to Aristotle,
what makes humans human “has no other cause. Man has many causes:
"animal," "twofooted," etc.; but nevertheless, man is in
virtue of himself man (καθ᾽αὑτὸν ἄνθρωπος ὁ ἄνθρωπός ἐστι)”.[15]
“Animal”, “twofooted” are here the “causes” that, so to say, make up a species
and determine a certain being to be the way they are κατὰ τὸ γένος (we could
say that a kiwi has many causes: “bird”, “flightless” etc.). Similarly, even
the lack of essential traits as such is possible only in virtue of
the humanity of the human themselves. A human can be concretely “without
language” only because they are human in the first place, even if we assumed
that language is what makes humans human. (Notice how, despite the stark contrast
with Hull’s assumption behind his talk of horses and zebras, that the organism
has no essence, the conclusion is the same: traits do not make horses more
“horse” nor humans more “human”.)
The
argument is clearly circular - and here’s the strength and the weakness of essentialism:
human essence is so empty it can include everyone – even the supposedly
inhuman; at the same time, it grants us no knowledge of universally shared
specific essential traits.
Hull
says: “On [...] rare occasions babies are born with little in the way of a
cerebrum. If there is a significant sense in which they nevertheless retain the
potentiality for language use, it eludes me”[16].
According to Hull, such a condition would constitute a case for abnormality in
essentialism: “Organisms that lack a particular trait actually possess it potentially
or else are abnormal for not possessing it”[17]. Now
we understand where the problem resides. In this lack, in fact, the
essentialist sees neither a formal possibility (a chimp could have a different
DNA[18],
not because it is a chimp, but because we consider the trait abstractly, as we
have seen in the first concept of στέρησις) nor just a concrete possibility (as
in the case of a man that can concretely be affected by the accident of blindness because of
violence, illness etc.[19]),
but the contingency of the human individual as such: de individuo non est scientia, because no matter how atypical and
lacking, it remains, a priori, human.
Essence
proper, in its circularity, is so
inclusive that it neutralises variations. We can now see how it does not do the
crucial evolutionary sense of diversity justice. The real problem of the normality/abnormality
discourse, from the point of view of the evolutionary critique of essentialism,
is not (just) its supposed exclusionary character, but its abstractness. As
Hull repeatedly states, variations, ab-normalities and so on constitute biological species.[20]
A
possible solution to fill the
emptiness of the essence is to look at statistical norms – normal developmental
pathways[21],
or perhaps those traits which happen “to be prevalent and important for the
moment”[22],
adaptations, functions etc.[23]
When we look at normality from the point of view of evolutionary biology,
however, we do not find anything that resembles a norm or an archetype – and
it’s not just a matter of extension. What is the statistical norm (e.g. an
adaptation) in a species, ours included, is always contextual, both in space (for example, it depends on the
environment in which organisms develop as on the organisms’ developmental
plasticity[24])
and in time (“all alleles which we now possess were once more than just rare:
they were unique”[25]).
Even if, for a moment in the species’ evolutionary history, a trait is de facto universal, it never depends
only on, say, humans themselves (strongly contradicting Aristotle’s
aforementioned claim).
A functional account of normality as essence
is no less fallacious. What’s the normal, real function of a hand? What is the
function of sex? Hull’s implicit reference to the notion of functional
cooptation shows us how every variation in functioning is equally abnormal and
normal.[26]
From the perspective of commonsense
biology, human non-reproductives such as old maids and priests may be biologically
abnormal, but from the perspective of professional biology, they need not be.[27]
To sum it up, given the
immense variability of humans, in the quest for human nature, it is not useful
to stretch essences to absolute inclusivity (paradoxically making them
extremely rigid: Aristotle’s living species are eternal). “Nor does it help to
switch from traditional essences to statistically characterized essences.”[28]
The first strategy eventually fails the explicative/causal role of essences,
while the second, despite being explicative for some humans, fails their universal semantic role.
III – New essentialism
In
light of the impasses of traditional essentialism, a new essentialism has been
proposed in the last 20 years.[29]
This view hopes to conciliate the discourse about essences with the importance
of history and variations for evolutionary biology. I will present it briefly
through Samir Okasha’s proposal for a relational view of essences in his 2002
paper Darwinian metaphysics: species and
the question of essentialism.
Okasha
shows how Darwinism does not just discard intrinsic essences, but also a
specific conception of biological traits:
modern biology offers no grounds whatever
for supposing that intra-specific variation is confined to some particular set
of “accidental” traits, leaving an invariant shared essence. On the contrary,
Darwinism leads us to expect variation with respect to all organismic traits,
morphological, physiological, behavioural and genetic.[30]
If there are no core-traits,
variations are not merely indifferent accidents, and the living is therefore
not an essentially-defined ὑποκείμενον, but the product of a causal history of
variations and of a context-dependent development. No Homo sapiens or Balænoptera
musculus has an intrinsic human or whale core that makes them so.
How
are humans and whales part of their own species then? In Okasha’s words, “on
the most popular accounts of the species concept found in contemporary
evolutionary biology, organisms are assigned to species on the basis of
relational properties”[31].
For example, organisms are part of the same species because they’re part of a
“group of interbreeding natural populations that are reproductively isolated
from other such groups”[32]
(Mayr’s biological concept), or of the same ecological niche (they exploit the
same resources and habitats, according to van Valen’s ecological concept[33]),
or because they instantiate “particular chunks of the genealogical nexus,
bounded by speciation events and extinction events”[34]
(phylogenetic concept). None of the properties emphasised by these concepts are
intrinsic: “Two molecule-for-molecule identical organisms could in principle be
members of different species, on all of these species concepts”[35].
Incidentally, it is important to notice that different species concepts usually
are used in different theoretical and scientific contexts, and thus give us
potentially conflicting descriptions of the world.
This last paradoxical example
highlights a problematic character of relational essences, that is, their
indifference towards an organism's actual properties. Taken alone and in
itself, a whale is not really a
whale. Here Okasha reasons that if we replace essential intrinsic properties
“with whatever relational property we think determines species membership – we
do sever the semantic and causal/explanatory roles”[36]. Sure,
Balænoptera musculus will still refer
to a group of individuals relatively well determined in time and space – but no
species concept (biological, phylogenetic, ecological etc.) can exhaust why
whales have the traits that they have – or that can or could have. As the
causes will be found in different fields (for example, an adaptation can be
explained by natural selection, but its variations are also a matter of
developmental plasticity), species-defining relational properties are too
restrictive (“Morphology is indicative of that ability [interbreeding], but not
the causal outcome of it”[37])
and potentially in reciprocal contradiction. A whale, insofar as it is a Balænoptera
musculus, is never just itself, but an extended network of historical and
contingent non-specific causes. For this reason, Okasha (following Laporte,
1997) reasons that “the property in virtue of which any given organism belongs
to its species is a property the organism could have lacked”[38],
“properties that, at least in some cases, seem clearly accidental rather than
essential to the organisms which possess them”[39]. The
interbreeding and the ecological concepts rest on contingent events of
reproductive or ecological isolation that might just not occur, and the
phylogenetic concept still rests on the former non-temporal ones to define what
a speciation is.
Okasha’s
proposal of relational essences as merely semantic thus remains empty: to say
that the only essential character of a human is to belong to the contingent
causal network of unessential (reproductive, ecological etc.) properties we
call “Homo sapiens” is to say that
there is nothing essential about a human but its own unessentiality. As Marc
Ereshefsky put it: “relational essentialism does not resurrect biological
essentialism because it is not essentialism”[40].
IV – Innateness
If
the philosopher still wants to look at biology in their search for human nature,
then clearly, they cannot answer their question in terms of an all-encompassing
class-defining differentia specifica.
However, an answer could still be put in terms of innateness.
It is
uncontroversially true of all and (perhaps) only humans that they
are born from humans. While, as we have seen, this relational property is not
enough of an essence, it might still indicate where human nature can be found. The
question about human nature is, so to say, reinterpreted as the question about
the natural human: issues of extension and explanation (semantic and
explanatory role of essence) are discarded, since the essence does not
individuate a natural kind (which at best exists in the context of a theory[41])
but a human’s ownmost natural possession. One human’s nature is seen as what
they are “born – or conceived – with”, what is inherited and remains a
necessary and determining bedrock for further development. For this reason,
what we are asking here is not the (empirical) question about what is innate
and what is not, but whether we can find anything like an innateness at all,
let alone an innate human nature.
Philosophers
in search of human nature might find the notion of innateness particularly
appealing, for a number of reasons. Innate traits are seen as our natural
passively received possessions, as opposed to our (perhaps cultural) actively
acquired traits, and thus they sustain the idea of a human nature (and of
nature in general) as something existing behind
our backs. Consequently, we might interpret innateness both in a proximate
and in an ultimate sense (à la Ernst
Mayr[42]):
our nature resides in what is inherited, as an innate set of necessary
properties acting as a bedrock for further contingent development (already in
Aristotle, because “man is born from man”, the μορφή of humans is itself φύσις[43]);
our nature is the product of evolution.
In biology, on the contrary,
the notion of innateness is controversial. But while this might be more evident
at the level of phenotypic development (where the boundary between innate and
acquired is more blurred), it is the gene the best candidate for instantiating innate
traits. We will see how they do not do the job – neither as genes-for, nor in
themselves.
The
first issue concerns the ontological status of an innate trait. To say that we
are born (or conceived) with some form of inherited natural possession is to
assume that, from the first moment of our ontogenesis, we already possess
specific traits potentially: we
inherit such potential traits in the form of hereditary material, and we
actualise them during development. This is why, for example, in the
modern-synthetic interpretation of genes, such material has both an epistemic
primacy over the organism (genes are what causes the organism – in the form of
“coding for”) and an ontological one (the genes themselves are actualized in
the organism, as it survives and reproduces – in the form of “expression”).
Now,
the informations composing the developed trait are, so to say, dispersed in a
network of interrelated causes – genes, epigenes, environment, experiences etc.
“The idea that genes ‘carry information’ about phenotypes in a special sense
which distinguishes them from other causes is [...] a highly contested idea”[44]
in contemporary biology. For example, in temperature-dependent sex
determination, “environmental signals carry information about sex in the same
unproblematic [...] sense as the SRY gene”[45]. Genes
alone, abstracted from this developmental network, are ineffective (“All
the genes can code for, if they code for anything, is the primary structure
(amino acid sequence) of a protein”[46]). Most
importantly though, it is hard to see how they are something belonging to the
organism at all, if the living organism as such has no relationship with
them whatsoever. In truth, the same holds for any other unit of transmission.
For example, the environment minus its effects on the organism simply is not
the environment that determines the development of the same organism. Similarly,
something merely present in one’s body is far from being a cause for the
organism, let alone its nature. What this shows us is that, in a sense, there
is nothing behind our backs, at least in the sense of (proximate) innate
natural possessions waiting to be developed. Everything is always, so to say,
in front of the developing organism.
Still,
the crucial notion of adaptation seems
to imply that something is, in fact, not only inherited, but it is so in a
relatively and functionally unchanging way (fitness
is heritable[47]),
and thus constitutes a good candidate for innateness. While the fitness of the
parent does not immediately imply the fitness of the offspring, it is the same
fitness that is supposed to be rebuilt by the organism’s network of genetic,
epigenetic, environmental, and even behavioural and social causes. In this
sense, we might find innateness in the adaptations we receive from the millions
of years of evolution. And yet, the attribution of adaptation to something
preceding us – in other words, the interpretation of adaptation as something
passively received and contextually re-enacted (with uncertain results) – is
problematic. Adaptation (as the production of adaptive traits) might be
considered as an in-development process – surely allowed by inherited causes
(genes, or an environmental niche), but not in itself innate. This holds for
potentially all living beings. According to geneticist Eva Jablonka, this is
shown, for example, by the notions of canalisation (the buffering of
developmental pathways from environmental and genetic variations) and adaptive
plasticity (the ability of genes of developing different phenotypes according
to the environment)[48]: “Biochemical,
neural and behavioural exploration can generate several alternative routes that
all end in the same dynamically stable state. [...] Canalization, therefore,
necessarily implies plasticity. Adaptive plasticity, on the other hand,
requires that some processes are canalized”[49] – the
same adaptation can be reconstructed differently in different generations, and
“The response to new conditions can be reversible or irreversible, adaptive or
nonadaptive, active or passive, continuous or discontinuous”[50].
Jablonka
has recently emphasised how this sense of adaptation is particularly evident in
humans:
At the conceptual level, acknowledging the
existence of epigenetic inheritance renders the classical nature-nurture
dichotomy obsolete, because it means that heredity (‘nature’) can be
developmentally constructed (‘nurtured’). The ‘biosocial’ entails reciprocal
interactions between biological and sociological factors, showing, in this
case, both how social processes impact epigenetic ones and how epigenetic effects
impact the social for both the directly induced generation and for descendent
generations[51].
As the keyword “biosocial” is
potentially extendable to the whole hominid evolution thanks to the historical
study of the culture/epigenetics interactions[52], it is
hard to see how the search for the “innate” can grant us any access to
something like a natural possession, existing before human actions, overdetermining them. During their
development as living beings, humans both give shape to what they transmit and
reconstruct what they have inherited, potentially putting it into question.
This is what Jablonka means by epigenetic inheritance as extended plasticity: as “developmentally induced epigenetic changes
can be heritable for few or many generations, [...] plasticity can therefore
have a temporal (hereditary) dimension” blurring the distinction “between
ontogenetic plasticity and heredity”[53]. The
notion of a (remote) innate nature fails here too: the very constitution of heritage
is a transgenerational active process, as the human organism receives nothing
passively.
V – Conclusions
Do
humans have a nature at all – distinguishing them from other living beings, or
individuating a natural and more fundamental side in humans? Biology seems to
answer negatively. As evolutionary biology undermines the idea of nature both
as essence and as cause, humans appear, like any other species, as contingent
and self-determining beings. They have no essence, and no nature overdetermines
them. Far from delegitimizing it, this rebuke forces us to rethink the question
itself. Searching for an answer in another field (dismissing the biological in
favour of the Spirit, of the technological, the religious etc.) only ignores
the problem. Why do we ask about human nature, and why do we look at biology as
its appropriate place? What does this lack of nature – our evolutionary and
developmental contingency – say about our questioning? Perhaps, if the essence
and cause of the living is nothing like a nature, we will have to restructure
the relationship between nature and life from scratch.
References
Aristotle, Metaphysics.
Aristotle, Physics.
M. Ereshefsky, 2010, What's Wrong with the New Biological
Essentialism, in Philosophy of
Science 77, 5, pp. 674-85.
M Ereshefsky, Species, 2010, on https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/species/.
A. Borghini, E. Casetta,
2012, Quel che resta dei generi naturali,
in Rivista di estetica 49, pp.
247-271-
P. Griffiths, S. Linquist,
2021, The Distinction Between Innate and
Acquired Characteristics, on https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/innate-acquired/.
D. Hull, On Human Nature, 1986, in PSA:
Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association
1986, 2, pp. 3-13.
L. Illetterati, Declinazioni del concetto di natura tra
ontologia e storia, available on https://www.youtube.com/user/AccademiaIISF.
E. Jablonka, 2016, Cultural epigenetics, in The Sociological Review Monographs 64,
1, pp. 42–60.
R. Lewontin, 1970, The units of selection, in Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics
1, pp. 1-18.
E. Mayr, 1961, Cause and effect in biology, in Science 134, 3489, pp. 1501-1506.
S. Okasha, 2002, Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the
question of essentialism, in Synthese
131, pp. 191-213.
[1] See Aristotle, Physics, 192b.
[2] L. Illetterati, Declinazioni del concetto di natura tra ontologia e storia, Paesaggi contemporanei.
[3] See Okasha, 2002, pp.
191-192.
[4] See for example ivi, p. 203.
[5] Hull, 1986, p. 4.
[6] Ivi, p. 5.
[7] Ibidem.
[8] Ivi, p. 6.
[9] Ivi, p. 7.
[10] Ibidem.
[11] Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1022 b 22-27, available on http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/; my emphasis.
[12] In
this modern use, we might translate γένος
as species or a higher taxon. For example, the Apteryx genus (understood
essentialistically) is flightless, so an individual Apteryx australis
would be flightless according to the essence of its genus.
[13] See ivi, 1022 a 25-30.
[14] Cfr.
ivi, 1022 b 30-33.
[15] Ivi, 1022 a 30-35.
[16] Hull, 1986, p. 7.
[17] Ibidem.
[18] Ivi, p. 5.
[19] Metaphysics 1022 b 30-35; 1046 a 35-36.
[20] Hull, 1896, p. 10.
[21] Ivi, p. 8.
[22] Ivi, p. 9.
[23] Ibidem.
[24] Ivi, p. 8.
[25] Ivi, p. 9.
[26] “An organ evolved to perform
a function might be commandeered to perform another”, ibidem.
[27] Ivi, p. 10.
[28] Ivi, p. 11.
[29] See M. Ereshefsky, Species, on https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/species/,
2010.
[30] Okasha, 2002, p. 197.
[31] Ivi, p. 199.
[32] Mayr, 1968, quoted in ivi,
p. 200.
[33] Ibidem.
[34] Ibidem.
[35] Ivi, p. 201.
[36] Ivi, p. 203.
[37] Ivi, p. 204.
[38] Ivi, p. 205.
[39] Ivi, p. 206.
[40] Ereshefsky, 2010, p. 683.
[41] See for example A. Borghini, E. Casetta,
2012: “i generi naturali sono convenzioni fissate su proprietà [...] inserite
in una rete causale appropriata [...] cioè che ruota intorno a un centro
definito dalla nostra miglior teoria”, pp. 267-268.
[42] Mayr, 1961.
[43] Aristotle, Phys., 193b.
[44] P. Griffiths, S. Linquist, The Distinction Between Innate and Acquired
Characteristics, on https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/innate-acquired/, 2021.
[45] Ibidem.
[46] Godfrey-Smith, 1999, p. 328, in ivi.
[47] Lewontin, 1970.
[48] Jablonka,
2016, p. 43
[49] Ivi, p. 45.
[50] Ibidem.
[51] Ivi, p. 55.
[52] Ivi, p. 53.
[53] Ivi, p. 55.
Commenti
Posta un commento